The playwright George Bernard Shaw (1856-1950) once remarked,
“There is only one religion, though there are hundreds of versions of it.” We,
however, live in an age that is far more pluralistic than Shaw’s ever was, a
world where relativity reigns supreme. Pluralism, the belief that truth is not
singular or unitary (Hinman 382); relativism, the belief that values are relative
to a particular culture or group and cannot be judged outside that culture or
group (Hinman 35); and subjectivism, an extreme form of relativism which
affirms that each individual's beliefs are relative to that individual alone
and cannot be judged from the outside by anyone else (Hinman 383), have been
around for a long time, and come in assorted flavors such as the polytheisms of
Hinduism and ancient Rome, pantheism, the sophists, and the views of Friedrich
Nietzsche and Søren Kierkegaard, to name a few. These views are very popular in
American academic institutions, where professors adopt relativistic views in
order to teach different cultures and religions.
Unfortunately, when relativistic pedagogies are applied to
religious studies, a subject that is clouded by meaningless terms and bipolar
assumptions about religion, serious problems ensue. The assumption that all
religions are the same or equal because they all supposedly teach similar
principles is illogical and dangerous. The differences between “religions” are
so many and so crucial that it is impossible to define what “religion” even is.
This flawed approach also disregards and distorts history, including the merits
and demerits of religions; discourages students from thinking critically about
religion; and ignores the fact that all religions operate under different
moralities and have certain agendas that they want fulfilled. And the means by
which religions fulfill their agendas has serious philosophical, political,
social, and economic implications as well.
Most of my religious studies professors at UTEP asserted that all
religions are equal (though they antagonized western religious traditions,
Christianity in particular). But this is by no means a local or even a regional
issue. In Living Religions, a textbook assigned for my major world
religions class, Mary Pat Fisher explains that “some liberal scholars are . . .
proposing that there is an underlying experiential unity among religions.
Wilfred Cantwell Smith, for instance, concluded that the revelations of all
religions have come from the same divine source. Christian theologian John Hick
suggests that religions are culturally different responses to one and the same
reality. The Muslim scholar Frithjof Schuon feels that there is a common
mystical base underlying all religions” (482). Conservative scholars,
furthermore, have recognized the relativistic trends in American institutions
of higher education. "There are university professors today who are so
enamored of academic freedom and so devoted to an endless search for
truth," writes Dr. Gordon H. Clark, former Chairman of the Department of
Philosophy at Butler University for 28 years, "that they are antagonistic
to those who say they have found some. Possessing truth, in their view, is a
violation of academic freedom" (99). Dr. Michael P. Lynch, associate
professor of philosophy at the University of Connecticut, argues:
Under the banner of postmodernism, cynicism about truth and related notions like objectivity and knowledge has become the semiofficial philosophical stance of many academic disciplines. Roughly speaking, the attitude is that objective truth is an illusion and what we call truth is just another name for power. Consequently, if truth is valuable at all, it is valuable--as power is--merely as means. (2004)
Why have academic institutions adapted views that undermine their
very purpose? According to columnist and political commentator John Leo, “One
factor is that colleges now stress the need for each identity group to express
its ‘voice’ or ‘narrative,’ without much scruple about whether the narratives
are literally true. (Postmodern theory says there is no such thing as truth
anyway.)” (2000). What do we need universities for, then, if knowledge is
merely a matter of personal interpretation? And if truth is just another name
for power, and the goal of universities is to preserve and promote truth,
doesn’t that mean that we should oppose them for being oppressive?
To compound the problem further, it is impossible to adequately
define the term religion because “religions” are simply too
different. The etymology of religion is itself uncertain,
stemming anywhere from "bond between humans and gods," "monastic
life," "careful," or "go through again, read again"
(“Religion”). Every religious studies textbook I have read acknowledges that
religion is practically impossible to define. Dr. Clark argues that “the more
definite the definition [of religion] is, the more clearly the writers are not
writing on the same subject. . . . If the term God is so
broadened as to include the usage of both Spinoza and the animists, the term
and the definition of religion in which it is used become
meaningless” (110, 119). In a textbook assigned for my philosophy of religion
class, Exploring the Philosophy of Religion, David
Stewart notes that defining religion “is difficult due to the
diversity of meanings [the term] has acquired” and “the wide diversity of
religious traditions” (1). Stewart himself offers no definition. "Religion
is therefore such a complex and elusive topic," notes Fisher, "that
some contemporary scholars of religion are seriously questioning whether
'religion' or 'religions' can be studied at all. They have determined that no
matter where they try to grab the thing, other parts will get away" (1).
How then can there be "religions," yet no "religion"?
In Anatomy of the Sacred: An Introduction to Religion,
which was assigned for my introduction to religious studies course, James
Livingston remarks that, even though religion is a universal human phenomenon,
“Why, after all, should we think that the many religions of the world have some
‘essence’ in common? There are legions of particular religions, but perhaps no
such thing as ‘religion’” (7). He proposes to define religion as
“that system of activities and beliefs directed toward that which is perceived
to be of sacred value and transforming power” (10). While this is a noble
attempt, there are many problems with this definition, for the term sacred is
left intentionally vague in order to include almost any inspiring belief or
practice. The term transforming power is also vague, for if I
believe that watching television is a “sacred” rite that makes me a better
person, I have established my own religion. Many more irreligious practices and
beliefs can be applied to this definition—the very thing Livingston was trying
to avoid—but religious traditions that either believe everything is sacred or
don’t care to make a distinction between the sacred and the profane, such as
pantheism, Buddhism, and Confucianism, don’t fit the definition very well
either. Livingston, moreover, ironically argues in direct contrast to the
professor who assigned his textbook:
To be self-conscious and reflective about our beliefs does not mean, of course, that we become so open that our minds begin to resemble the proverbial sieve that cannot retain anything and through which all beliefs pass as though equally true and valuable. That is spiritual promiscuity. Our temptation today appears to be to fall into either an uncritical and slothful relativism or an uncritical and slothful dogmatism. (15)
The problem is twofold. One one hand, there are those who think
that all religions are essentially the same; on the other there are those who
dogmatically claim that their religion is the only true one—though they might
not know what their own religion teaches—while all others are arbitrarily
declared false. Both views, as Livingston comments, are uncritical and lazy.
Attempting to classify religions logically "fails because the
divergences have occurred through no logical principles" (Clark 123). Some
argue that the differences between religions are not substantial. But
overlooking religious differences has dangerous consequences. “The failure of
the U.S. government to grasp fully the religious dimensions of the conflicts in
Southeast Asia and Iran explains, in part, our serious miscalculations and
errors of judgment in those regions in recent history” (Livingston 13). The
Bible, for example, teaches that Jesus Christ alone is God and the only way to
eternal salvation (Jn. 14.6), thus regarding all other beliefs that are
contrary to what He teaches as false (cf. Lk. 11.23, Jn. 8.24, Acts 4.12); that
men should lead but are equal to women (1 Cor. 11, Gal. 3.28); that believers
are to love their neighbors as well as their enemies (Lev. 19.18; Matt. 5,
19.19; Rom. 13); and that the Kingdom of God “is not of this world. If My
[Christ’s] kingdom were of this world, then My servants would be fighting so
that I would not be handed over to the Jews; but as it is, My kingdom is not of
this realm" (Jn. 18.36). The Koran, on the other hand, deliberately
rejects Christianity and teaches that it is blasphemy to worship Jesus as God
(Surah 5:16-17), codifies rape and spousal abuse (Surah 2:223, 4:34), and
orders Muslims to distrust and kill unbelievers, including Christians (Surah
5:50, 9:5), and to conquer the whole world under Islam (Surah 61:9, 48:28,
9:33), all of which directly contradict the teachings of the Bible. After looking
at only two religions, it is evident that they are fundamentally different;
they are, in fact, diametrically opposed, even though they both come from
Judaism! The only way to argue that all religions are the same is to ignore
what they actually teach.
Others argue that it is better to assume all religions are equal
in academic settings in order to analyze them "impartially" and avoid
offending people. So, rather than letting the students develop their critical
thinking skills and evaluate each religion for themselves, the judgment is
already made for them. They are discouraged from asking questions like, In what
sense are all religions equal? In a moral sense? How is this possible, when
every religion has its own moral code that contradicts another’s? Satanism, for
example, teaches that pride, selfishness, and indulging in sexual immorality
are all good things, while Christianity teaches the opposite. Professors should
not have to lie about what religions teach for the sake of not offending
students. Being honest about history can help us avoid repeating the mistakes
of history.
It is important to recognize that religions are vastly different
from each other—irreconcilably different—and their teachings often contradict
one another. A subject as serious as religion cannot simply be blanketed with
false or inadequate assumptions that obscure the differences between them. I
urge professors to evaluate their assumptions about religion and to consider an
honest, straightforward, and perhaps more philosophical approach to teaching
religious studies. They may not agree with any of the religions they discuss,
but that doesn't mean they should change or disregard what the religions
themselves teach and have taught historically in order to make them all equal
and only superficially different. Professors should ensure that their own
assumptions about religion do not distort the religions they teach; instead,
they should explain the assumptions that each religion holds to, for every
religion has its own ideology. A philosophical approach to studying religion
would be far more fruitful, for philosophy, as William James characterizes it,
is "the unusually stubborn attempt to think clearly." Thinking
clearly about religion is very important in our interconnected world. To study
religion philosophically, Stewart explains, “is to analyze critically the
fundamental issues raised by religion and to subject these issues to rigorous
scrutiny" (2). Using a philosophical approach, teachers can start by
identifying a religion’s assumptions and then explain how that religion
implicitly or explicitly derives its beliefs and practices from those
assumptions in order to create an ideology or worldview, because every
religion, regardless of whether it emphasizes doctrine, emotions, or mystical
encounters, offers a way of viewing and experiencing the present world and
possibly the world to come. In any case, I also urge students to question the
assertions that professors make regarding matters of religion and to
investigate religions for themselves, especially by seeking out primary
sources. These issues are far too important to overlook.
_________________________________________
Works Cited
- Clark, Gordon H. Three
Types of Religious Philosophy. Rpt. in Christian Philosophy:
The Works of Gordon Haddon Clark. Ed. John W. Robbins. Vol. 4. Unicoi:
Trinity Foundation, 2004. 15-103. Print.
- ----. Religion, Reason, and
Revelation. Rpt. in Christian
Philosophy: The Works of Gordon Haddon Clark. Ed. John W. Robbins.
Vol. 4. Unicoi: Trinity Foundation, 2004. 107-270. Print.
- Fisher, Mary Pat. Living
Religions. 6th ed. Upper Saddle River: Prentice Hall, 2005. Print.
- Hinman, Lawrence M. Ethics:
A Pluralistic Approach to Moral Theory. 3rd ed. Belmont: Wadsworth,
2003. Print.
- Leo, John. "Race and
gender games on campus." The Washington Times 1 June
2000, final ed. (Commentary): A14. LexisNexis Academic. Web. 4
Apr. 2012.
- Livingston, James C. Anatomy
of the Sacred: An Introduction to Religion. 5th ed.
Upper Saddle River: Prentice Hall, 2005. Print.
- Lynch, Michael P. "Who
Cares About The Truth?" Chronicle Of Higher Education 51.3
(2004): B6-B8. Academic Search Complete. Web. 7 Apr. 2012.
- “Religion.” Online
Etymology Dictionary. Douglas Harper, 2012. Web. 4 Apr. 2012.
- Stewart, David. Exploring
the Philosophy of Religion. 7th ed. Upper Saddle
River: Pearson, 2010. Print.
No comments:
Post a Comment